|
|
As
mentioned in the introductory
paragraph to the primary text, the two Soul and Body poems
vary mainly in two ways: firstly, there are differences in phrasing, but
since most of the alternatives are synonymous, there is no real change
of meaning. Secondly, the fragmented address of the saved soul to its
body is only found in the Vercelli
Book version, Soul and Body I, not in Soul and Body
II, which is part of the Exeter
Book. Both manuscripts were written in the second half of the
tenth century, placing their common source before then. Because of the
similarity of the two texts, I will discuss here the more complete Soul
and Body I as representative for both versions.
|
|
No single
source is known for the poem. The poet seems rather to have picked out
elements from different sources and combined them into a more dramatic
argument, supporting his main - didactic - message: Be prepared!
First of
all, the poet provides a setting. He reminds his readers that death will
surely come and that 'it is necessary for every man to consider for himself
the journey his soul will have to make .'
The soul will receive 'either torment or glory' from the moment of death
to Judgement Day, and thus be judged twice at death and at the
final Judgement .
No. 69 of the Sermones ad fratres
shares this view and gives a vivid description of
|
|
|
|
the first
incident .
This view of a double judgement was expressed by such important characters
as Gregory the Great
and Caesarius of Arles ,
who both had immense influence on Anglo-Saxon Christian thought. There
are some difficulties connected with this view, though, as Shippey describes :
First of all, a more or less final judgement at the point of death 'makes
Judgement Day something of a formality' .
I do not agree that this is necessarily so. Bede,
for example, gives a convincing explanation for a second judgement in
a paragraph on the martyrs under the throne of God in his Explanatio
Apocalypsis .
This explanation stands for the multitudes of the righteous and the sinners
as well. Secondly, it is only the soul which is judged at death. Body
and soul together will have to answer for their deeds only on Judgement
Day itself. The idea of double judgement was competed with, however, by
a theory that all souls went to limbo after death and waited there together
until Judgement Day .
The saints, of course, were excepted from this. This leads us to the next
problem to which Shippey points: If the fate of the soul is irreversibly
decided right after death, 'ecclesiastical intercession for the dead is
of no help' .
This leaves no room for masses for the dead.
In Soul
and Body I, the poet now introduces the damned soul, which leaves
hell every seventh night in order to visit its body .
The source for this is very probably the Visio
Pauli ,
a work belonging to the NT
Apocrypha and of disputable reputation. Even though this text was
strongly opposed in learned circles, it nevertheless enjoyed high popularity
throughout the Middle Ages. While the holiday occurs once a year on Easter
Day in the original version, it became a weekly day and night of refreshment
in the shortened versions .
The poet of Soul and Body I includes some original ideas, and thus
changes the underlying meaning of the incident. The soul in the poem does
not simply take some time off, but goes to visit its body, while the souls
in the Visio are only intended to return to their bodies at the
resurrection of the dead .
The soul in the Anglo-Saxon poem does not even return on its own account,
but is forced to do so: 'and your soul will often have to seek you out
- against my own will - and say foul things to you, just as you did them
to me' .
In the Visio, this day and night off - reduced to a night in the
poem - is an act of pity. The poet only considered the symptom, not the
cause. This also becomes clear in the return of the saved soul, which
is an original element of the writer, used as an explanation of the saved
soul's return and for the opposition of the two situations.
|
|